content_id
stringlengths
14
14
page_title
stringlengths
1
250
section_title
stringlengths
1
1.26k
breadcrumb
stringlengths
1
1.39k
text
stringlengths
9
3.55k
c_yyf8a91sb8zd
Uniqueness case
Summary
Uniqueness_case
In mathematical finite group theory, the uniqueness case is one of the three possibilities for groups of characteristic 2 type given by the trichotomy theorem. The uniqueness case covers groups G of characteristic 2 type with e(G) ≥ 3 that have an almost strongly p-embedded maximal 2-local subgroup for all primes p whose 2-local p-rank is sufficiently large (usually at least 3). Aschbacher (1983a, 1983b) proved that there are no finite simple groups in the uniqueness case.
c_wiuqw5s7m1eg
Vertex of a representation
Summary
Vertex_of_a_representation
In mathematical finite group theory, the vertex of a representation of a finite group is a subgroup associated to it, that has a special representation called a source. Vertices and sources were introduced by Green (1958–1959).
c_ak0r69vi6z84
No free lunch theorem
Summary
No_free_lunch_theorem
In mathematical folklore, the "no free lunch" (NFL) theorem (sometimes pluralized) of David Wolpert and William Macready, alludes to the saying "no such thing as a free lunch", that is, there are no easy shortcuts to success. It appeared in the 1997 "No Free Lunch Theorems for Optimization". Wolpert had previously derived no free lunch theorems for machine learning (statistical inference).In 2005, Wolpert and Macready themselves indicated that the first theorem in their paper "state that any two optimization algorithms are equivalent when their performance is averaged across all possible problems".The "no free lunch" (NFL) theorem is an easily stated and easily understood consequence of theorems Wolpert and Macready actually prove. It is weaker than the proven theorems, and thus does not encapsulate them. Various investigators have extended the work of Wolpert and Macready substantively. In terms of how the NFL theorem is used in the context of the research area, the no free lunch in search and optimization is a field that is dedicated for purposes of mathematically analyzing data for statistical identity, particularly search and optimization.While some scholars argue that NFL conveys important insight, others argue that NFL is of little relevance to machine learning research.
c_zmcv9slvsx6y
Kimeme
Algorithm design
Kimeme > Features > Algorithm design
In mathematical folklore, the no free lunch theorem (sometimes pluralized) of David Wolpert and William G. Macready appears in the 1997 "No Free Lunch Theorems for Optimization. "This mathematical result states the need for a specific effort in the design of a new algorithm, tailored to the specific problem to be optimized. Kimeme allows the design and experimentation of new optimization algorithms through the new paradigm of memetic computing, a subject of computational intelligence which studies algorithmic structures composed of multiple interacting and evolving modules (memes).
c_y178lgcbs02q
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
In mathematical formulas, the ± symbol may be used to indicate a symbol that may be replaced by either the plus and minus signs, + or −, allowing the formula to represent two values or two equations.If x2 = 9, one may give the solution as x = ±3. This indicates that the equation has two solutions: x = +3 and x = −3. A common use of this notation is found in the quadratic formula x = − b ± b 2 − 4 a c 2 a , {\displaystyle x={\frac {-b\pm {\sqrt {b^{2}-4ac}}}{2a}},} which describes the two solutions to the quadratic equation ax2+bx+c = 0. Similarly, the trigonometric identity sin ⁡ ( A ± B ) = sin ⁡ ( A ) cos ⁡ ( B ) ± cos ⁡ ( A ) sin ⁡ ( B ) {\displaystyle \sin(A\pm B)=\sin(A)\cos(B)\pm \cos(A)\sin(B)} can be interpreted as a shorthand for two equations: one with + on both sides of the equation, and one with − on both sides.
c_et1ak5c099j0
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
+ x 5 5 ! − x 7 7 !
c_5nsft66jssul
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
+ ⋯ ± 1 ( 2 n + 1 ) ! x 2 n + 1 + ⋯ . {\displaystyle \sin \left(x\right)=x-{\frac {x^{3}}{3!
c_v396ql0ee8fw
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
}}+{\frac {x^{5}}{5! }}-{\frac {x^{7}}{7! }}+\cdots \pm {\frac {1}{(2n+1)!
c_nnkx2ii5jj9r
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
}}x^{2n+1}+\cdots ~.} Here, the plus-or-minus sign indicates that the term may be added or subtracted depending on whether n is odd or even; a rule which can be deduced from the first few terms. A more rigorous presentation would multiply each term by a factor of (−1)n, which gives +1 when n is even, and −1 when n is odd.
c_t5rhdpv0dla3
Minus-plus sign
In mathematics
Plus–minus_sign > Usage > In mathematics
In older texts one occasionally finds (−)n, which means the same. When the standard presumption that the plus-or-minus signs all take on the same value of +1 or all −1 is not true, then the line of text that immediately follows the equation must contain a brief description of the actual connection, if any, most often of the form "where the ‘±’ signs are independent" or similar. If a brief, simple description is not possible, the equation must be re-written to provide clarity; e.g. by introducing variables such as s1, s2, ... and specifying a value of +1 or −1 separately for each, or some appropriate relation, like s 3 = s 1 ⋅ ( s 2 ) n , {\displaystyle s_{3}=s_{1}\cdot (s_{2})^{n}\,,} or similar.
c_93zq8lrn6u68
Penrose inequality
Summary
Penrose_inequality
In mathematical general relativity, the Penrose inequality, first conjectured by Sir Roger Penrose, estimates the mass of a spacetime in terms of the total area of its black holes and is a generalization of the positive mass theorem. The Riemannian Penrose inequality is an important special case. Specifically, if (M, g) is an asymptotically flat Riemannian 3-manifold with nonnegative scalar curvature and ADM mass m, and A is the area of the outermost minimal surface (possibly with multiple connected components), then the Riemannian Penrose inequality asserts m ≥ A 16 π . {\displaystyle m\geq {\sqrt {\frac {A}{16\pi }}}.}
c_f1n0z6ykaaxg
Penrose inequality
Summary
Penrose_inequality
This is purely a geometrical fact, and it corresponds to the case of a complete three-dimensional, space-like, totally geodesic submanifold of a (3 + 1)-dimensional spacetime. Such a submanifold is often called a time-symmetric initial data set for a spacetime. The condition of (M, g) having nonnegative scalar curvature is equivalent to the spacetime obeying the dominant energy condition.
c_lsirgjald43t
Penrose inequality
Summary
Penrose_inequality
This inequality was first proved by Gerhard Huisken and Tom Ilmanen in 1997 in the case where A is the area of the largest component of the outermost minimal surface. Their proof relied on the machinery of weakly defined inverse mean curvature flow, which they developed. In 1999, Hubert Bray gave the first complete proof of the above inequality using a conformal flow of metrics. Both of the papers were published in 2001.
c_q789s4bz4c5i
Bernstein algebra
Summary
Bernstein_problem_in_mathematical_genetics
In mathematical genetics, a genetic algebra is a (possibly non-associative) algebra used to model inheritance in genetics. Some variations of these algebras are called train algebras, special train algebras, gametic algebras, Bernstein algebras, copular algebras, zygotic algebras, and baric algebras (also called weighted algebra). The study of these algebras was started by Ivor Etherington (1939). In applications to genetics, these algebras often have a basis corresponding to the genetically different gametes, and the structure constant of the algebra encode the probabilities of producing offspring of various types. The laws of inheritance are then encoded as algebraic properties of the algebra. For surveys of genetic algebras see Bertrand (1966), Wörz-Busekros (1980) and Reed (1997).
c_qztcsv96vslb
Higman-Sims graph
Summary
Higman-Sims_graph
In mathematical graph theory, the Higman–Sims graph is a 22-regular undirected graph with 100 vertices and 1100 edges. It is the unique strongly regular graph srg(100,22,0,6), where no neighboring pair of vertices share a common neighbor and each non-neighboring pair of vertices share six common neighbors. It was first constructed by Mesner (1956) and rediscovered in 1968 by Donald G. Higman and Charles C. Sims as a way to define the Higman–Sims group, a subgroup of index two in the group of automorphisms of the Higman–Sims graph.
c_n1nvd2wbi5o0
3-transposition group
Summary
3-transposition_group
In mathematical group theory, a 3-transposition group is a group generated by a conjugacy class of involutions, called the 3-transpositions, such that the product of any two involutions from the conjugacy class has order at most 3. They were first studied by Bernd Fischer (1964, 1970, 1971) who discovered the three Fischer groups as examples of 3-transposition groups.
c_vevaozxmv6ym
C-group
Summary
C-group
In mathematical group theory, a C-group is a group such that the centralizer of any involution has a normal Sylow 2-subgroup. They include as special cases CIT-groups where the centralizer of any involution is a 2-group, and TI-groups where any Sylow 2-subgroups have trivial intersection. The simple C-groups were determined by Suzuki (1965), and his classification is summarized by Gorenstein (1980, 16.4). The classification of C-groups was used in Thompson's classification of N-groups. The simple C-groups are the projective special linear groups PSL2(p) for p a Fermat or Mersenne prime the projective special linear groups PSL2(9) the projective special linear groups PSL2(2n) for n≥2 the projective special linear groups PSL3(q) for q a prime power the Suzuki groups Sz(22n+1) for n≥1 the projective unitary groups PU3(q) for q a prime power
c_c87kg8n4g9vi
Demushkin group
Summary
Demushkin_group
In mathematical group theory, a Demushkin group (also written as Demuškin or Demuskin) is a pro-p group G having a certain properties relating to duality in group cohomology. More precisely, G must be such that the first cohomology group with coefficients in Fp = Z/p Z has finite rank, the second cohomology group has rank 1, and the cup product induces a non-degenerate pairing H1(G,Fp)× H1(G,Fp) → H2(G,Fp).Such groups were introduced by Demuškin (1959). Demushkin groups occur as the Galois groups of the maximal p-extensions of local number fields containing all p-th roots of unity.
c_exnt22hj9qiu
Normal p-complement
Summary
P-nilpotent_group
In mathematical group theory, a normal p-complement of a finite group for a prime p is a normal subgroup of order coprime to p and index a power of p. In other words the group is a semidirect product of the normal p-complement and any Sylow p-subgroup. A group is called p-nilpotent if it has a normal p-complement.
c_ppjvpsbonm83
Special abelian subgroup
Summary
Special_abelian_subgroup
In mathematical group theory, a subgroup of a group is termed a special abelian subgroup or SA-subgroup if the centralizer of any nonidentity element in the subgroup is precisely the subgroup(Curtis & Reiner 1981, p.354). Equivalently, an SA subgroup is a centrally closed abelian subgroup. Any SA subgroup is a maximal abelian subgroup, that is, it is not properly contained in another abelian subgroup. For a CA group, the SA subgroups are precisely the maximal abelian subgroups.SA subgroups are known for certain characters associated with them termed exceptional characters.
c_k9515ivgpvy5
Tame group
Summary
Tame_group
In mathematical group theory, a tame group is a certain kind of group defined in model theory. Formally, we define a bad field as a structure of the form (K, T), where K is an algebraically closed field and T is an infinite, proper, distinguished subgroup of K, such that (K, T) is of finite Morley rank in its full language. A group G is then called a tame group if no bad field is interpretable in G.
c_rvclinxpsdcw
Hall–Higman theorem
Summary
Hall–Higman_theorem
In mathematical group theory, the Hall–Higman theorem, due to Philip Hall and Graham Higman (1956, Theorem B), describes the possibilities for the minimal polynomial of an element of prime power order for a representation of a p-solvable group.
c_fis02p4wqglx
Schur cover
Summary
Schur_multiplier
In mathematical group theory, the Schur multiplier or Schur multiplicator is the second homology group H 2 ( G , Z ) {\displaystyle H_{2}(G,\mathbb {Z} )} of a group G. It was introduced by Issai Schur (1904) in his work on projective representations.
c_pjehhdga13xl
Automorphism group of a free group
Summary
Automorphism_group_of_a_free_group
In mathematical group theory, the automorphism group of a free group is a discrete group of automorphisms of a free group. The quotient by the inner automorphisms is the outer automorphism group of a free group, which is similar in some ways to the mapping class group of a surface.
c_gfo6ooudq94p
Balance theorem
Summary
Balance_theorem
In mathematical group theory, the balance theorem states that if G is a group with no core then G either has disconnected Sylow 2-subgroups or it is of characteristic 2 type or it is of component type (Gorenstein 1983, p. 7). The significance of this theorem is that it splits the classification of finite simple groups into three major subcases.
c_5nd6rbtrxlby
Root data
Summary
Root_datum
In mathematical group theory, the root datum of a connected split reductive algebraic group over a field is a generalization of a root system that determines the group up to isomorphism. They were introduced by Michel Demazure in SGA III, published in 1970.
c_nkwvo4tkbocr
Green's function number
Summary
Green's_function_number
In mathematical heat conduction, the Green's function number is used to uniquely categorize certain fundamental solutions of the heat equation to make existing solutions easier to identify, store, and retrieve.
c_gx60uskl35uh
Perpetuant
Summary
Perpetuant
In mathematical invariant theory, a perpetuant is informally an irreducible covariant of a form or infinite degree. More precisely, the dimension of the space of irreducible covariants of given degree and weight for a binary form stabilizes provided the degree of the form is larger than the weight of the covariant, and the elements of this space are called perpetuants. Perpetuants were introduced and named by Sylvester (1882, p.105). MacMahon (1884, 1885, 1894) and Stroh (1890) classified the perpetuants.
c_mq3j531oid1j
Perpetuant
Summary
Perpetuant
Elliott (1907) describes the early history of perpetuants and gives an annotated bibliography. MacMahon conjectured and Stroh proved that the dimension of the space of perpetuants of degree n>2 and weight w is the coefficient of xw of x 2 n − 1 − 1 ( 1 − x 2 ) ( 1 − x 3 ) ⋯ ( 1 − x n ) {\displaystyle {\frac {x^{2^{n-1}-1}}{(1-x^{2})(1-x^{3})\cdots (1-x^{n})}}} For n=1 there is just one perpetuant, of weight 0, and for n=2 the number is given by the coefficient of xw of x2/(1-x2). There are very few papers after about 1910 discussing perpetuants; (Littlewood 1944) is one of the few exceptions. (Kraft & Procesi 2020) exhibited an explicit base of the space of perpetuants.
c_a2ltk9yo1rrm
Transvectant
Summary
Transvectant
In mathematical invariant theory, a transvectant is an invariant formed from n invariants in n variables using Cayley's Ω process.
c_7kdx9ojzebg7
Evectant
Summary
Evectant
In mathematical invariant theory, an evectant is a contravariant constructed from an invariant by acting on it with a differential operator called an evector. Evectants and evectors were introduced by Sylvester (1854, p.95).
c_tjsfo7g8ztzm
Invariant of a binary form
Summary
Invariants_of_binary_form
In mathematical invariant theory, an invariant of a binary form is a polynomial in the coefficients of a binary form in two variables x and y that remains invariant under the special linear group acting on the variables x and y.
c_8uaognnplxym
Canonizant
Summary
Canonizant
In mathematical invariant theory, the canonizant or canonisant is a covariant of forms related to a canonical form for them.
c_mw1d7w456sqx
Catalecticant
Summary
Catalecticant
In mathematical invariant theory, the catalecticant of a form of even degree is a polynomial in its coefficients that vanishes when the form is a sum of an unusually small number of powers of linear forms. It was introduced by Sylvester (1852); see Miller (2010). The word catalectic refers to an incomplete line of verse, lacking a syllable at the end or ending with an incomplete foot.
c_pry42kdmesja
Osculant
Summary
Osculant
In mathematical invariant theory, the osculant or tacinvariant or tact invariant is an invariant of a hypersurface that vanishes if the hypersurface touches itself, or an invariant of several hypersurfaces that osculate, meaning that they have a common point where they meet to unusually high order.
c_hdn6e4ykd1f2
74 knot
Summary
74_knot
In mathematical knot theory, 74 is the name of a 7-crossing knot which can be visually depicted in a highly-symmetric form, and so appears in the symbolism and/or artistic ornamentation of various cultures.
c_y4yzmru03fp6
Conway sphere
Summary
Conway_sphere
In mathematical knot theory, a Conway sphere, named after John Horton Conway, is a 2-sphere intersecting a given knot or link in a 3-manifold transversely in four points. In a knot diagram, a Conway sphere can be represented by a simple closed curve crossing four points of the knot, the cross-section of the sphere; such a curve does not always exist for an arbitrary knot diagram of a knot with a Conway sphere, but it is always possible to choose a diagram for the knot in which the sphere can be depicted in this way. A Conway sphere is essential if it is incompressible in the knot complement. Sometimes, this condition is included in the definition of Conway spheres. == References ==
c_l5bcz1hcs78g
Link (knot theory)
Summary
Link_(knot_theory)
In mathematical knot theory, a link is a collection of knots which do not intersect, but which may be linked (or knotted) together. A knot can be described as a link with one component. Links and knots are studied in a branch of mathematics called knot theory. Implicit in this definition is that there is a trivial reference link, usually called the unlink, but the word is also sometimes used in context where there is no notion of a trivial link.
c_53y99gt7o86j
Link (knot theory)
Summary
Link_(knot_theory)
For example, a co-dimension 2 link in 3-dimensional space is a subspace of 3-dimensional Euclidean space (or often the 3-sphere) whose connected components are homeomorphic to circles. The simplest nontrivial example of a link with more than one component is called the Hopf link, which consists of two circles (or unknots) linked together once. The circles in the Borromean rings are collectively linked despite the fact that no two of them are directly linked. The Borromean rings thus form a Brunnian link and in fact constitute the simplest such link.
c_ogips1fqd5mb
Hopf link
Summary
Hopf_link
In mathematical knot theory, the Hopf link is the simplest nontrivial link with more than one component. It consists of two circles linked together exactly once, and is named after Heinz Hopf.
c_q71ykl3gofzh
Equisatisfiability
Summary
Equisatisfiability
In mathematical logic (a subtopic within the field of formal logic), two formulae are equisatisfiable if the first formula is satisfiable whenever the second is and vice versa; in other words, either both formulae are satisfiable or both are not. Equisatisfiable formulae may disagree, however, for a particular choice of variables. As a result, equisatisfiability is different from logical equivalence, as two equivalent formulae always have the same models.
c_vrkl2kut5feg
Equisatisfiability
Summary
Equisatisfiability
Whereas within equisatisfiable formulae, only the primitive proposition the formula imposes is valued. Equisatisfiability is generally used in the context of translating formulae, so that one can define a translation to be correct if the original and resulting formulae are equisatisfiable. Examples of translations involving this concept are Skolemization and some translations into conjunctive normal form.
c_ernahugexvqf
Valuation (logic)
Mathematical logic
Valuation_(logic) > Mathematical logic
In mathematical logic (especially model theory), a valuation is an assignment of truth values to formal sentences that follows a truth schema. Valuations are also called truth assignments. In propositional logic, there are no quantifiers, and formulas are built from propositional variables using logical connectives.
c_2vni3jgt2pdu
Valuation (logic)
Mathematical logic
Valuation_(logic) > Mathematical logic
In this context, a valuation begins with an assignment of a truth value to each propositional variable. This assignment can be uniquely extended to an assignment of truth values to all propositional formulas. In first-order logic, a language consists of a collection of constant symbols, a collection of function symbols, and a collection of relation symbols.
c_i2mz1cwtjw96
Valuation (logic)
Mathematical logic
Valuation_(logic) > Mathematical logic
Formulas are built out of atomic formulas using logical connectives and quantifiers. A structure consists of a set (domain of discourse) that determines the range of the quantifiers, along with interpretations of the constant, function, and relation symbols in the language. Corresponding to each structure is a unique truth assignment for all sentences (formulas with no free variables) in the language.
c_fzrmhkzdb9nu
Resolution inference
Summary
First-order_resolution
In mathematical logic and automated theorem proving, resolution is a rule of inference leading to a refutation complete theorem-proving technique for sentences in propositional logic and first-order logic. For propositional logic, systematically applying the resolution rule acts as a decision procedure for formula unsatisfiability, solving the (complement of the) Boolean satisfiability problem. For first-order logic, resolution can be used as the basis for a semi-algorithm for the unsatisfiability problem of first-order logic, providing a more practical method than one following from Gödel's completeness theorem. The resolution rule can be traced back to Davis and Putnam (1960); however, their algorithm required trying all ground instances of the given formula. This source of combinatorial explosion was eliminated in 1965 by John Alan Robinson's syntactical unification algorithm, which allowed one to instantiate the formula during the proof "on demand" just as far as needed to keep refutation completeness.The clause produced by a resolution rule is sometimes called a resolvent.
c_kw6bfezbgqeq
Summary
Turnstile_(symbol)
In mathematical logic and computer science the symbol ⊢ ( ⊢ {\displaystyle \vdash } ) has taken the name turnstile because of its resemblance to a typical turnstile if viewed from above. It is also referred to as tee and is often read as "yields", "proves", "satisfies" or "entails".
c_elyf3hdf76bu
Gabbay's separation theorem
Summary
Gabbay's_separation_theorem
In mathematical logic and computer science, Gabbay's separation theorem, named after Dov Gabbay, states that any arbitrary temporal logic formula can be rewritten in a logically equivalent "past → future" form. I.e. the future becomes what must be satisfied. This form can be used as execution rules; a MetateM program is a set of such rules. == References ==
c_118525g6llis
Mu-recursive function
Summary
Mu-recursive_function
In mathematical logic and computer science, a general recursive function, partial recursive function, or μ-recursive function is a partial function from natural numbers to natural numbers that is "computable" in an intuitive sense – as well as in a formal one. If the function is total, it is also called a total recursive function (sometimes shortened to recursive function). In computability theory, it is shown that the μ-recursive functions are precisely the functions that can be computed by Turing machines (this is one of the theorems that supports the Church–Turing thesis). The μ-recursive functions are closely related to primitive recursive functions, and their inductive definition (below) builds upon that of the primitive recursive functions.
c_yw3mbukrfglv
Mu-recursive function
Summary
Mu-recursive_function
However, not every total recursive function is a primitive recursive function—the most famous example is the Ackermann function. Other equivalent classes of functions are the functions of lambda calculus and the functions that can be computed by Markov algorithms. The subset of all total recursive functions with values in {0,1} is known in computational complexity theory as the complexity class R.
c_8cgw3qvm2pxp
Univalence axiom
Summary
Higher_inductive_type
In mathematical logic and computer science, homotopy type theory (HoTT ) refers to various lines of development of intuitionistic type theory, based on the interpretation of types as objects to which the intuition of (abstract) homotopy theory applies. This includes, among other lines of work, the construction of homotopical and higher-categorical models for such type theories; the use of type theory as a logic (or internal language) for abstract homotopy theory and higher category theory; the development of mathematics within a type-theoretic foundation (including both previously existing mathematics and new mathematics that homotopical types make possible); and the formalization of each of these in computer proof assistants. There is a large overlap between the work referred to as homotopy type theory, and as the univalent foundations project.
c_kqnqpt1xgj7k
Univalence axiom
Summary
Higher_inductive_type
Although neither is precisely delineated, and the terms are sometimes used interchangeably, the choice of usage also sometimes corresponds to differences in viewpoint and emphasis. As such, this article may not represent the views of all researchers in the fields equally. This kind of variability is unavoidable when a field is in rapid flux.
c_pgwr14muxwi5
Top type
Summary
Top_type
In mathematical logic and computer science, some type theories and type systems include a top type that is commonly denoted with top or the symbol ⊤. The top type is sometimes called also universal type, or universal supertype as all other types in the type system of interest are subtypes of it, and in most cases, it contains every possible object of the type system. It is in contrast with the bottom type, or the universal subtype, which every other type is supertype of and it is often that the type contains no members at all.
c_5xuxzguq6qba
Kleene star
Summary
Kleene_star
In mathematical logic and computer science, the Kleene star (or Kleene operator or Kleene closure) is a unary operation, either on sets of strings or on sets of symbols or characters. In mathematics, it is more commonly known as the free monoid construction. The application of the Kleene star to a set V {\displaystyle V} is written as V ∗ {\displaystyle V^{*}} . It is widely used for regular expressions, which is the context in which it was introduced by Stephen Kleene to characterize certain automata, where it means "zero or more repetitions".
c_7v9pxc0djz0i
Kleene star
Summary
Kleene_star
If V {\displaystyle V} is a set of strings, then V ∗ {\displaystyle V^{*}} is defined as the smallest superset of V {\displaystyle V} that contains the empty string ε {\displaystyle \varepsilon } and is closed under the string concatenation operation. If V {\displaystyle V} is a set of symbols or characters, then V ∗ {\displaystyle V^{*}} is the set of all strings over symbols in V {\displaystyle V} , including the empty string ε {\displaystyle \varepsilon } .The set V ∗ {\displaystyle V^{*}} can also be described as the set containing the empty string and all finite-length strings that can be generated by concatenating arbitrary elements of V {\displaystyle V} , allowing the use of the same element multiple times. If V {\displaystyle V} is either the empty set ∅ or the singleton set { ε } {\displaystyle \{\varepsilon \}} , then V ∗ = { ε } {\displaystyle V^{*}=\{\varepsilon \}} ; if V {\displaystyle V} is any other finite set or countably infinite set, then V ∗ {\displaystyle V^{*}} is a countably infinite set. As a consequence, each formal language over a finite or countably infinite alphabet Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } is countable, since it is a subset of the countably infinite set Σ ∗ {\displaystyle \Sigma ^{*}} . The operators are used in rewrite rules for generative grammars.
c_g7wdu4a6wexk
Calculus of Constructions
Summary
Calculus_of_Inductive_Constructions
In mathematical logic and computer science, the calculus of constructions (CoC) is a type theory created by Thierry Coquand. It can serve as both a typed programming language and as constructive foundation for mathematics. For this second reason, the CoC and its variants have been the basis for Coq and other proof assistants. Some of its variants include the calculus of inductive constructions (which adds inductive types), the calculus of (co)inductive constructions (which adds coinduction), and the predicative calculus of inductive constructions (which removes some impredicativity).
c_c7m22j7nswnm
Lambda-mu calculus
Summary
Lambda-mu_calculus
In mathematical logic and computer science, the lambda-mu calculus is an extension of the lambda calculus introduced by M. Parigot. It introduces two new operators: the μ operator (which is completely different both from the μ operator found in computability theory and from the μ operator of modal μ-calculus) and the bracket operator. Proof-theoretically, it provides a well-behaved formulation of classical natural deduction. One of the main goals of this extended calculus is to be able to describe expressions corresponding to theorems in classical logic.
c_uui5zih03bff
Lambda-mu calculus
Summary
Lambda-mu_calculus
According to the Curry–Howard isomorphism, lambda calculus on its own can express theorems in intuitionistic logic only, and several classical logical theorems can't be written at all. However with these new operators one is able to write terms that have the type of, for example, Peirce's law. Semantically these operators correspond to continuations, found in some functional programming languages.
c_k3b44wxsv67t
Two-variable logic with counting
Summary
Two-variable_logic_with_counting
In mathematical logic and computer science, two-variable logic is the fragment of first-order logic where formulae can be written using only two different variables. This fragment is usually studied without function symbols.
c_yrkc2q2o60to
Analytical hierarchy
Summary
Analytical_hierarchy
In mathematical logic and descriptive set theory, the analytical hierarchy is an extension of the arithmetical hierarchy. The analytical hierarchy of formulas includes formulas in the language of second-order arithmetic, which can have quantifiers over both the set of natural numbers, N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } , and over functions from N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } to N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } . The analytical hierarchy of sets classifies sets by the formulas that can be used to define them; it is the lightface version of the projective hierarchy.
c_ws5ljpkjxpvp
Implication graph
Summary
Implication_graph
In mathematical logic and graph theory, an implication graph is a skew-symmetric, directed graph G = (V, E) composed of vertex set V and directed edge set E. Each vertex in V represents the truth status of a Boolean literal, and each directed edge from vertex u to vertex v represents the material implication "If the literal u is true then the literal v is also true". Implication graphs were originally used for analyzing complex Boolean expressions.
c_w8b47n4kr7nx
Potential isomorphism
Summary
Potential_isomorphism
In mathematical logic and in particular in model theory, a potential isomorphism is a collection of finite partial isomorphisms between two models which satisfies certain closure conditions. Existence of a partial isomorphism entails elementary equivalence, however the converse is not generally true, but it holds for ω-saturated models.
c_mz23ddu2plqu
Universal Horn theory
Summary
Universal_Horn_theory
In mathematical logic and logic programming, a Horn clause is a logical formula of a particular rule-like form which gives it useful properties for use in logic programming, formal specification, and model theory. Horn clauses are named for the logician Alfred Horn, who first pointed out their significance in 1951.
c_96qtjxzbzzmi
Completeness (logic)
Summary
Completeness_(logic)
In mathematical logic and metalogic, a formal system is called complete with respect to a particular property if every formula having the property can be derived using that system, i.e. is one of its theorems; otherwise the system is said to be incomplete. The term "complete" is also used without qualification, with differing meanings depending on the context, mostly referring to the property of semantical validity. Intuitively, a system is called complete in this particular sense, if it can derive every formula that is true.
c_7uj5b2om3zdn
Skolem paradox
Summary
Skolem_paradox
In mathematical logic and philosophy, Skolem's paradox is a seeming contradiction that arises from the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem. Thoralf Skolem (1922) was the first to discuss the seemingly contradictory aspects of the theorem, and to discover the relativity of set-theoretic notions now known as non-absoluteness. Although it is not an actual antinomy like Russell's paradox, the result is typically called a paradox and was described as a "paradoxical state of affairs" by Skolem (1922: p.
c_s33uvyqvvl6v
Skolem paradox
Summary
Skolem_paradox
295). Skolem's paradox is that every countable axiomatisation of set theory in first-order logic, if it is consistent, has a model that is countable. This appears contradictory because it is possible to prove, from those same axioms, a sentence that intuitively says (or that precisely says in the standard model of the theory) that there exist sets that are not countable.
c_5a834ri7i3zu
Skolem paradox
Summary
Skolem_paradox
Thus the seeming contradiction is that a model that is itself countable, and which therefore contains only countable sets, satisfies the first-order sentence that intuitively states "there are uncountable sets". A mathematical explanation of the paradox, showing that it is not a contradiction in mathematics, was given by Skolem (1922). Skolem's work was harshly received by Ernst Zermelo, who argued against the limitations of first-order logic, but the result quickly came to be accepted by the mathematical community.
c_wsi6kh0nb6hy
Skolem paradox
Summary
Skolem_paradox
The philosophical implications of Skolem's paradox have received much study. One line of inquiry questions whether it is accurate to claim that any first-order sentence actually states "there are uncountable sets". This line of thought can be extended to question whether any set is uncountable in an absolute sense. More recently, the paper "Models and Reality" by Hilary Putnam, and responses to it, led to renewed interest in the philosophical aspects of Skolem's result.
c_w3u21j6y48d8
Collapsing function
Summary
Collapsing_function
In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining (notations for) certain recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give names to certain ordinals much larger than the one being defined, perhaps even large cardinals (though they can be replaced with recursively large ordinals at the cost of extra technical difficulty), and then "collapse" them down to a system of notations for the sought-after ordinal. For this reason, ordinal collapsing functions are described as an impredicative manner of naming ordinals. The details of the definition of ordinal collapsing functions vary, and get more complicated as greater ordinals are being defined, but the typical idea is that whenever the notation system "runs out of fuel" and cannot name a certain ordinal, a much larger ordinal is brought "from above" to give a name to that critical point.
c_dd90lo24zrkl
Collapsing function
Summary
Collapsing_function
An example of how this works will be detailed below, for an ordinal collapsing function defining the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (i.e., defining a system of notations up to the Bachmann–Howard ordinal). The use and definition of ordinal collapsing functions is inextricably intertwined with the theory of ordinal analysis, since the large countable ordinals defined and denoted by a given collapse are used to describe the ordinal-theoretic strength of certain formal systems, typically subsystems of analysis (such as those seen in the light of reverse mathematics), extensions of Kripke–Platek set theory, Bishop-style systems of constructive mathematics or Martin-Löf-style systems of intuitionistic type theory. Ordinal collapsing functions are typically denoted using some variation of either the Greek letter ψ {\displaystyle \psi } (psi) or θ {\displaystyle \theta } (theta).
c_szisawowvdly
Ordinal notation
Summary
Ordinal_notation
In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal notation is a partial function mapping the set of all finite sequences of symbols, themselves members of a finite alphabet, to a countable set of ordinals. A Gödel numbering is a function mapping the set of well-formed formulae (a finite sequence of symbols on which the ordinal notation function is defined) of some formal language to the natural numbers. This associates each well-formed formula with a unique natural number, called its Gödel number. If a Gödel numbering is fixed, then the subset relation on the ordinals induces an ordering on well-formed formulae which in turn induces a well-ordering on the subset of natural numbers.
c_hbsygajvmqvi
Ordinal notation
Summary
Ordinal_notation
A recursive ordinal notation must satisfy the following two additional properties: the subset of natural numbers is a recursive set the induced well-ordering on the subset of natural numbers is a recursive relationThere are many such schemes of ordinal notations, including schemes by Wilhelm Ackermann, Heinz Bachmann, Wilfried Buchholz, Georg Cantor, Solomon Feferman, Gerhard Jäger, Isles, Pfeiffer, Wolfram Pohlers, Kurt Schütte, Gaisi Takeuti (called ordinal diagrams), Oswald Veblen. Stephen Cole Kleene has a system of notations, called Kleene's O, which includes ordinal notations but it is not as well behaved as the other systems described here. Usually one proceeds by defining several functions from ordinals to ordinals and representing each such function by a symbol.
c_yeznq96dv6pp
Ordinal notation
Summary
Ordinal_notation
In many systems, such as Veblen's well known system, the functions are normal functions, that is, they are strictly increasing and continuous in at least one of their arguments, and increasing in other arguments. Another desirable property for such functions is that the value of the function is greater than each of its arguments, so that an ordinal is always being described in terms of smaller ordinals. There are several such desirable properties. Unfortunately, no one system can have all of them since they contradict each other.
c_twsyd5l85fjp
Minsky machine
Summary
Minsky_machine
In mathematical logic and theoretical computer science, a register machine is a generic class of abstract machines used in a manner similar to a Turing machine. All the models are Turing equivalent.
c_ksi9zdg0mk5x
Convergent term rewriting system
Summary
Abstract_rewriting
In mathematical logic and theoretical computer science, an abstract rewriting system (also (abstract) reduction system or abstract rewrite system; abbreviated ARS) is a formalism that captures the quintessential notion and properties of rewriting systems. In its simplest form, an ARS is simply a set (of "objects") together with a binary relation, traditionally denoted with → {\displaystyle \rightarrow } ; this definition can be further refined if we index (label) subsets of the binary relation. Despite its simplicity, an ARS is sufficient to describe important properties of rewriting systems like normal forms, termination, and various notions of confluence.
c_rxcru5fd1jnz
Convergent term rewriting system
Summary
Abstract_rewriting
Historically, there have been several formalizations of rewriting in an abstract setting, each with its idiosyncrasies. This is due in part to the fact that some notions are equivalent, see below in this article. The formalization that is most commonly encountered in monographs and textbooks, and which is generally followed here, is due to Gérard Huet (1980).
c_8uqb63h257ym
Lambda cube
Summary
Lambda_cube
In mathematical logic and type theory, the λ-cube (also written lambda cube) is a framework introduced by Henk Barendregt to investigate the different dimensions in which the calculus of constructions is a generalization of the simply typed λ-calculus. Each dimension of the cube corresponds to a new kind of dependency between terms and types. Here, "dependency" refers to the capacity of a term or type to bind a term or type. The respective dimensions of the λ-cube correspond to: x-axis ( → {\displaystyle \rightarrow } ): types that can bind terms, corresponding to dependent types.
c_vznrpqueur2c
Lambda cube
Summary
Lambda_cube
y-axis ( ↑ {\displaystyle \uparrow } ): terms that can bind types, corresponding to polymorphism. z-axis ( ↗ {\displaystyle \nearrow } ): types that can bind types, corresponding to (binding) type operators.The different ways to combine these three dimensions yield the 8 vertices of the cube, each corresponding to a different kind of typed system. The λ-cube can be generalized into the concept of a pure type system.
c_k1ic5vx9d3hn
Löwenheim number
Summary
Löwenheim_number
In mathematical logic the Löwenheim number of an abstract logic is the smallest cardinal number for which a weak downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem holds. They are named after Leopold Löwenheim, who proved that these exist for a very broad class of logics.
c_xkesrom7e758
Theory of pure equality
Summary
Theory_of_pure_equality
In mathematical logic the theory of pure equality is a first-order theory. It has a signature consisting of only the equality relation symbol, and includes no non-logical axioms at all.This theory is consistent but incomplete, as a non-empty set with the usual equality relation provides an interpretation making certain sentences true. It is an example of a decidable theory and is a fragment of more expressive decidable theories, including monadic class of first-order logic (which also admits unary predicates and is, via Skolem normal form, related to set constraints in program analysis) and monadic second-order theory of a pure set (which additionally permits quantification over predicates and whose signature extends to monadic second-order logic of k successors).
c_c8nw7ovtlxwy
Beth definability
Summary
Beth_definability
In mathematical logic, Beth definability is a result that connects implicit definability of a property to its explicit definability. Specifically Beth definability states that the two senses of definability are equivalent. First-order logic has the Beth definability property.
c_qkbn0tq4ev3y
Craig interpolation
Summary
Craig_interpolation
In mathematical logic, Craig's interpolation theorem is a result about the relationship between different logical theories. Roughly stated, the theorem says that if a formula φ implies a formula ψ, and the two have at least one atomic variable symbol in common, then there is a formula ρ, called an interpolant, such that every non-logical symbol in ρ occurs both in φ and ψ, φ implies ρ, and ρ implies ψ. The theorem was first proved for first-order logic by William Craig in 1957. Variants of the theorem hold for other logics, such as propositional logic. A stronger form of Craig's interpolation theorem for first-order logic was proved by Roger Lyndon in 1959; the overall result is sometimes called the Craig–Lyndon theorem.
c_9cyi99ypd68l
Craig's theorem
Summary
Craig's_theorem
In mathematical logic, Craig's theorem (also known as Craig's trick) states that any recursively enumerable set of well-formed formulas of a first-order language is (primitively) recursively axiomatizable. This result is not related to the well-known Craig interpolation theorem, although both results are named after the same logician, William Craig.
c_syi6v2dp3b99
Diaconescu theorem
Summary
Diaconescu's_theorem
In mathematical logic, Diaconescu's theorem, or the Goodman–Myhill theorem, states that the full axiom of choice is sufficient to derive the law of the excluded middle or restricted forms of it. The theorem was discovered in 1975 by Radu Diaconescu and later by Goodman and Myhill. Already in 1967, Errett Bishop posed the theorem as an exercise (Problem 2 on page 58 in Foundations of constructive analysis).
c_r6uc4nhqy2l3
Frege's propositional calculus
Summary
Frege's_propositional_calculus
In mathematical logic, Frege's propositional calculus was the first axiomatization of propositional calculus. It was invented by Gottlob Frege, who also invented predicate calculus, in 1879 as part of his second-order predicate calculus (although Charles Peirce was the first to use the term "second-order" and developed his own version of the predicate calculus independently of Frege). It makes use of just two logical operators: implication and negation, and it is constituted by six axioms and one inference rule: modus ponens. Frege's propositional calculus is equivalent to any other classical propositional calculus, such as the "standard PC" with 11 axioms.
c_yvcc2ejrqn1k
Frege's propositional calculus
Summary
Frege's_propositional_calculus
Frege's PC and standard PC share two common axioms: THEN-1 and THEN-2. Notice that axioms THEN-1 through THEN-3 only make use of (and define) the implication operator, whereas axioms FRG-1 through FRG-3 define the negation operator.
c_whljmdm08z2j
Frege's propositional calculus
Summary
Frege's_propositional_calculus
The following theorems will aim to find the remaining nine axioms of standard PC within the "theorem-space" of Frege's PC, showing that the theory of standard PC is contained within the theory of Frege's PC. (A theory, also called here, for figurative purposes, a "theorem-space", is a set of theorems that are a subset of a universal set of well-formed formulas. The theorems are linked to each other in a directed manner by inference rules, forming a sort of dendritic network. At the roots of the theorem-space are found the axioms, which "generate" the theorem-space much like a generating set generates a group.)
c_p0yb2ywqyoer
Kirby–Paris theorem
Summary
Goodstein_sequence
In mathematical logic, Goodstein's theorem is a statement about the natural numbers, proved by Reuben Goodstein in 1944, which states that every Goodstein sequence eventually terminates at 0. Laurence Kirby and Jeff Paris showed that it is unprovable in Peano arithmetic (but it can be proven in stronger systems, such as second-order arithmetic). This was the third example of a true statement that is unprovable in Peano arithmetic, after the examples provided by Gödel's incompleteness theorem and Gerhard Gentzen's 1943 direct proof of the unprovability of ε0-induction in Peano arithmetic. The Paris–Harrington theorem gave another example.
c_2wvmv08b4rl8
Kirby–Paris theorem
Summary
Goodstein_sequence
Kirby and Paris introduced a graph-theoretic hydra game with behavior similar to that of Goodstein sequences: the "Hydra" (named for the mythological multi-headed Hydra of Lerna) is a rooted tree, and a move consists of cutting off one of its "heads" (a branch of the tree), to which the hydra responds by growing a finite number of new heads according to certain rules. Kirby and Paris proved that the Hydra will eventually be killed, regardless of the strategy that Hercules uses to chop off its heads, though this may take a very long time. Just like for Goodstein sequences, Kirby and Paris showed that it cannot be proven in Peano arithmetic alone.
c_6fyqk4i34ow1
Gödel's β function
Summary
Gödel's_β_function
In mathematical logic, Gödel's β function is a function used to permit quantification over finite sequences of natural numbers in formal theories of arithmetic. The β function is used, in particular, in showing that the class of arithmetically definable functions is closed under primitive recursion, and therefore includes all primitive recursive functions. The β function was introduced without the name in the proof of the first of Gödel's incompleteness theorems (Gödel 1931). The β function lemma given below is an essential step of that proof. Gödel gave the β function its name in (Gödel 1934).
c_hjcrcjvv2os4
Heyting arithmetic
Summary
Heyting_arithmetic
In mathematical logic, Heyting arithmetic H A {\displaystyle {\mathsf {HA}}} is an axiomatization of arithmetic in accordance with the philosophy of intuitionism. It is named after Arend Heyting, who first proposed it.
c_fkx473k7dlud
Lindenbaum's lemma
Summary
Lindenbaum's_lemma
In mathematical logic, Lindenbaum's lemma, named after Adolf Lindenbaum, states that any consistent theory of predicate logic can be extended to a complete consistent theory. The lemma is a special case of the ultrafilter lemma for Boolean algebras, applied to the Lindenbaum algebra of a theory.
c_t2w0hjofc3g2
Lindstrom's theorem
Summary
Lindström's_theorem
In mathematical logic, Lindström's theorem (named after Swedish logician Per Lindström, who published it in 1969) states that first-order logic is the strongest logic (satisfying certain conditions, e.g. closure under classical negation) having both the (countable) compactness property and the (downward) Löwenheim–Skolem property.Lindström's theorem is perhaps the best known result of what later became known as abstract model theory, the basic notion of which is an abstract logic; the more general notion of an institution was later introduced, which advances from a set-theoretical notion of model to a category-theoretical one. Lindström had previously obtained a similar result in studying first-order logics extended with Lindström quantifiers.Lindström's theorem has been extended to various other systems of logic, in particular modal logics by Johan van Benthem and Sebastian Enqvist.
c_m4vahwo0nazg
Löb's Theorem
Summary
Löb's_Theorem
In mathematical logic, Löb's theorem states that in Peano arithmetic (PA) (or any formal system including PA), for any formula P, if it is provable in PA that "if P is provable in PA then P is true", then P is provable in PA. If Prov(P) means that the formula P is provable, we may express this more formally as If P A ⊢ P r o v ( P ) → P {\displaystyle {\mathit {PA}}\vdash {\mathrm {Prov} (P)\rightarrow P}} then P A ⊢ P {\displaystyle {\mathit {PA}}\vdash P} .An immediate corollary (the contrapositive) of Löb's theorem is that, if P is not provable in PA, then "if P is provable in PA, then P is true" is not provable in PA. For example, "If 1 + 1 = 3 {\displaystyle 1+1=3} is provable in PA, then 1 + 1 = 3 {\displaystyle 1+1=3} " is not provable in PA.Löb's theorem is named for Martin Hugo Löb, who formulated it in 1955. It is related to Curry's paradox.
c_z2iyebfqa7nx
Morley rank
Summary
Morley_rank
In mathematical logic, Morley rank, introduced by Michael D. Morley (1965), is a means of measuring the size of a subset of a model of a theory, generalizing the notion of dimension in algebraic geometry.
c_ldthcj2lr6ii
Typed set theory
Summary
Typed_set_theory
In mathematical logic, New Foundations (NF) is an axiomatic set theory, conceived by Willard Van Orman Quine as a simplification of the theory of types of Principia Mathematica. Quine first proposed NF in a 1937 article titled "New Foundations for Mathematical Logic"; hence the name. Much of this entry discusses NF with urelements (NFU), an important variant of NF due to Jensen and clarified by Holmes. In 1940 and in a revision in 1951, Quine introduced an extension of NF sometimes called "Mathematical Logic" or "ML", that included proper classes as well as sets.
c_z0067ijyeq8i
Typed set theory
Summary
Typed_set_theory
New Foundations has a universal set, so it is a non-well-founded set theory. That is to say, it is an axiomatic set theory that allows infinite descending chains of membership, such as ... xn ∈ xn-1 ∈ ... ∈ x2 ∈ x1. It avoids Russell's paradox by permitting only stratifiable formulas to be defined using the axiom schema of comprehension. For instance, x ∈ y is a stratifiable formula, but x ∈ x is not. New Foundations is closely related to Russellian unramified typed set theory (TST), a streamlined version of the theory of types of Principia Mathematica with a linear hierarchy of types.
c_5ijy5ppmsw0q
Peano–Russell notation
Summary
Peano–Russell_notation
In mathematical logic, Peano–Russell notation was Bertrand Russell's application of Giuseppe Peano's logical notation to the logical notions of Frege and was used in the writing of Principia Mathematica in collaboration with Alfred North Whitehead: "The notation adopted in the present work is based upon that of Peano, and the following explanations are to some extent modelled on those which he prefixes to his Formulario Mathematico." (Chapter I: Preliminary Explanations of Ideas and Notations, page 4)
c_pbe6ylg8n1bt
Rosser's trick
Summary
Rosser's_trick
In mathematical logic, Rosser's trick is a method for proving Gödel's incompleteness theorems without the assumption that the theory being considered is ω-consistent (Smorynski 1977, p. 840; Mendelson 1977, p. 160). This method was introduced by J. Barkley Rosser in 1936, as an improvement of Gödel's original proof of the incompleteness theorems that was published in 1931. While Gödel's original proof uses a sentence that says (informally) "This sentence is not provable", Rosser's trick uses a formula that says "If this sentence is provable, there is a shorter proof of its negation".
c_n8tpkd0xwk1v
Russell paradox
Summary
Russel's_paradox
In mathematical logic, Russell's paradox (also known as Russell's antinomy) is a set-theoretic paradox published by the British philosopher and mathematician Bertrand Russell in 1901. Russell's paradox shows that every set theory that contains an unrestricted comprehension principle leads to contradictions. The paradox had already been discovered independently in 1899 by the German mathematician Ernst Zermelo. However, Zermelo did not publish the idea, which remained known only to David Hilbert, Edmund Husserl, and other academics at the University of Göttingen.